Before Camus: Gustave Le Bon on ‘The World in Revolt’
From the desk of Thomas F. Bertonneau on Thu, 2010-01-14 09:40
Albert Camus’ L’Homme revolté [Man in Revolt] or The Rebel (1951) is a milestone of postwar philosophical writing, widely admired for its diagnosis of a combat-shattered, God-deprived, ideologically disgruntled world. In The Rebel Camus (1913-1960) was distancing himself from Existentialism – that of Sartre, anyway – in favor of something more like a tradition-rooted perspective. Existentialism had already caricatured itself in the early 1950s so that its slogans might serve undergraduates and taxicab drivers. Camus quoted at length from Friedrich Nietzsche and Fyodor Dostoyevsky; he reiterated that modernity itself was askew and had become bitterly unsatisfying to those caught up in its tenacious grip. Despite his range of reference, however, Camus makes no mention in The Rebel of Gustave Le Bon (1841-1931), author of The Psychology of Revolution (1895) and The Crowd: A Study of the Popular Mind (1896). Nevertheless Le Bon’s sharp-eyed meditations prefigure Camus’ “Absurdist” critique of society and culture, but from a non-disgruntled and distinctly rightwing point of view. Le Bon’s World in Revolt: A Psychological Study of our Times (1920) even anticipated Camus’ title. Le Bon’s follow-up, Le déséquilibre du monde [The Disequilibrium of the World] (1923) offered a trope – that of vertigo – which the Existentialists, including Camus, would eagerly receive and exploit. Camus’ protagonist in The Stranger, Mersault, feels such dizziness just before he murders a random Arab on the Algerian beach.
Except for The Crowd, Le Bon’s work has largely disappeared from the
institutional memory. The Crowd
maintains a tenuous grip because of its debt-holding position in respect to the
work of René Girard. But because Le Bon belongs on the political right, his few
contemporary commentators treat him dismissively. The Wikipedia article on Le Bon
I. In The Psychology of Revolution, Le Bon advanced the
thesis that insurrectionary political movements, far from being rational as
they portray themselves, have much in common with religious upheavals and
sectarian furor. According to Le Bon the French Revolution needed careful
reanalysis from the standpoint of “ancestral influences, the laws which rule the
action of the crowd, data relating to the disaggregation of personality, mental
contagion, the foundation of beliefs, and the distinction between the various
forms of logic.” Above all, one could never take the French Revolution’s – or any
revolution’s – explanation of itself at face value. In the ecstatic
discourse of revolutionaries, whether sectarian or political, the triumph of
the cause never appears as other than the working-out of what Le Bon calls
“imperious fatality.” Objective investigation would necessarily treat
revolutionary self-explanation as suspect, bracketing all subjective iteration
of complaints and justifications while looking elsewhere for an understanding
of causes. Man in his conscious fullness, Le Bon says, is precisely the creature
who averts fatality; one should
never confuse him with the degraded being who merges himself with fatality to
share in its promised consummation. In Le Bon’s opinion, “The historians who
have judged the events of the French Revolution in the name of rational logic
could not comprehend them, since this form of logic did not dictate them.”
That revolution, generally
considered, follows a consistent pattern and so conforms to a describable
ontogeny or inner logic, Le Bon never denies; but revolutions never think
themselves through. Inwardly, revolutions
declare themselves to be remarkably irrational; they unfold, not logically, but
pathologically. In The Psychology,
Le Bon writes, “Although the Jacobin is a great reasoner, this does not mean that
he is in the least guided by reason.” Revolutions give riotous vent to
inarticulate resentment and frustration, as acted out by urban masses, and as
led by demagogues whose talent is mobilization of the mass through
crystallizing slogans that fit the passing moment. The demagogues, however, can
suffer re-infection from the atmosphere of irrational excitement that they
exacerbate. Mentally, insurrection and revolution tend to the lowest common
denominator.
Le Bon argues in The
Psychology that it is cultic enthusiasm,
which must already exist in simmering latency, rather than any kind of
programmatic reason, that makes a violent outburst successful. Insurrection and agitation therefore always exhibit
the traits of Dionysiac frenzy; they incline by their atavistic character
toward dramatic sacrificial gestures that satisfy the un-bottled lusts of the
rout. Of the year 1789 and its train, Le Bon writes: “That the Revolution was
potent indeed, that it made France accept the violence, the murders, the ruin
of a frightful civil war, that it finally defended itself victoriously against
a Europe in arms, was due to the fact that it had founded not a new system of
government but a new religion.” This new religion even proffered a
substitute-Trinity. Nevertheless, “the fraternity and liberty which [the
Revolution] proclaimed never seduced the peoples [but] equality became their
gospel: the pivot of socialism and of the entire evolution of modern ideas.” Goading
the mob to regard custom and the law as, by their mere existence, offenses against equality, the agitators excited it
“to regard itself as a victim and
to pillage, burn, and massacre, imagining that in so doing it was exercising a
right.” The fetish of equality, inflated
to the status of “an absolute truth,” imbued its adherents with murderous
intolerance.
As it was in 1789, so too was it
in the Sixteenth Century. Thus, “Violence, hatred, and persecution… were the
habitual accompaniments of the great political and religious revolutions,
notably of the Reformation and the French Revolution.”
Turning to The Crowd, where Le Bon distills into principles the range of
empirical observations in The Psychology, we find that the qualities that the historian associates with
insurrections and revolutions coincide with those that the sociologist or
psychologist associates with groups, mobs, and collectives. Crowds, which have
a low power of reason, move in response to slogans and images of the simplest
type; the convictions of crowds stem from childish feelings and inclinations,
not from ideas or arguments, which indeed arouse their impatience and
hostility. Le Bon writes: “When [the crowd’s] convictions are closely examined,
whether at epochs marked by fervent religious faith, or by great political
upheavals such as those of the last century, it is apparent that they always
assume a peculiar form which I cannot better define than by giving it the name
of a religious sentiment.” These words look forward to those of Girard, whose Violence
and the Sacred (1966) and other books
build, with much original development, on Le Bon’s insight.
In joining the crowd, as both Le
Bon and Girard posit, one submits to an
imagined power that acts from a perch beyond the limitations of morality and
restraint. Discarding conscience to merge with the mass, the subject falls
prone, in Le Bon’s words, to “worship of a being supposed superior, fear of the
power with which the being is credited, blind submission to its commands,
inability to discuss its dogmas, the desire to spread them, and a tendency to
consider as enemies all by whom they are not accepted.”
Le Bon remarks, anticipating an
objection, that, “a person is not religious solely when he worships a divinity,
but when he puts all the resources of his mind… and the whole-souled ardor of
fanaticism at the service of a cause [which] becomes the goal and guide of his
thoughts and actions.” Crowds not only feel themselves to be participants in a movement that subsumes them, but also they regard themselves
as the bearers or vessels of uniquely vouchsafed knowledge, “the secret of
earthly or eternal happiness.” Just this delight in putative knowledge
assimilates the secular utopian with the sectarian zealot: “The Jacobins of the
Reign of Terror were at bottom as religious as the Catholics of the
Inquisition,” sharing as they did the “intolerance and fanaticism that are the
necessary accompaniments of the religious sentiment.” Le Bon cites Fustel de
Coulanges on the sacred character of the Roman Empire, for whose multitudes the
reigning Caesar assumed a mantle of godhood. Le Bon adds that while modern
mass-politics has dispensed with the altar, the political leaders “have
statues, or their portraits are in the hands of their admirers, and the cult of
which they are the object is not notably different from that accorded to their
predecessors.”
In The Crowd as elsewhere Le Bon refers repeatedly to the French
Revolution, his most constant case-in-point. Adding a century to his
experience, modern readers can find supplementary evidence to support Le Bon’s
argument in the recent and contemporary ideological-collectivist movements. These
too tend toward “assuming the religious shape [that] obviates discussion.” Le
Bon addresses the corrosive effect of the crowd-mentality on language, whose
richness of distinctions threatens the solidarity of unanimous predilection. Because
“the power of words is bound up with the images they evoke, and is quite
independent of their real significance,” it follows, as Le Bon writes, that as
motivators of collective solidarity, “words whose sense is the most ill-defined
are sometimes those that possess the most influence.”(2)
II. Writing just after the imposition of the Versailles Treaty, Le Bon
discerned in the patterns of recent history, beginning with the cataclysm of
the French Revolution, a single fluctuating crisis of Western civilization. The
genealogy of troubles could be pushed back into history beyond the last one
hundred and thirty years before the second decade of the Twentieth Century. Le
Bon thus saw the French Revolution itself as springing from causes traceable to
Luther, Calvin, and the sectarian fervor that their teachings unleashed. The
World in Revolt articulates Le Bon’s historical and sociological
perceptions. The World War had fused the mobilized masses with the state,
reinforcing a pattern already many times rehearsed on European soil. Historically,
the separation of the temporal and spiritual dimensions and of the public and
private domains had distinguished the feudal order from the top-heavy imperial
order that predeceased it. Pope and king, bishop and baron: these authorities
stood apart, as separate realms in tension with one another. In this space of
such tension, a new type of independent person could emerge, shaped by Gospel
ethics, Gothic stubbornness, and the settled local dispensation. At the same time the market began to
assert itself and to generate wealth.
True independence is rare and
fleeting. That the independent-minded minority will exercise a dominant
influence on the society is, moreover, a proposition by no means guaranteed. De-differentiating
forces always threaten to overwhelm the ethical subject and to subdue his
stabilizing, productive influence. In the first two centuries before and in the
first five centuries after the First Christian Millennium, Islam constituted
the major external threat to Europe’s achievement, whereas, internally,
beginning eve before the Reformation, dissolution of the articulated social
forms through religious contagion constituted the danger.(3)
To Le Bon, in the moment just
after the war, the prospect appeared stark. Britain and France, with American
help, had achieved unexpected victory over Germany and Austria, but the war had
stimulated “State intervention,” which had acquired the character of dogma. Thus,
“According to the apostles of State intervention, the Government, by reason of
its supposed superiority, ought to control the complex of a nation’s industrial
and commercial activities, depriving citizens of initiative, and therefore of
liberty.” Once fully mobilized, the masses of a nation, having forfeited
independent thought and enjoying the intoxication of collective enthrallment,
resist de-mobilization. They cling rather to the de-individuated state that
absolves them of responsibility, mistaking the condition for liberty. It is the
liberty, perhaps, of a soldier on liberty –
a kind of strictly limited license under the certainty that someone higher in
rank remains in charge. Socialists, as Le Bon sees it, took advantage of the
situation, hectoring and sloganeering, to prevent a reversion to the status
quo ante; a widespread sense of perpetual
conflict, continuing beyond the armistice, served their crass cause.
“The world is at present,” The
Revolt would have it, “as much disturbed by
political beliefs as it was during the great religious movements: Islamism, the
Crusades, the Reformation, the wars of religion and many others.”
Socialism in particular, “the
Gospel according to Karl Marx,” constitutes a new intrusion of “contradictory
and irreducible mystic ideals” into the social mass, in which ideals that mass
then invests its “blind faith” even while its leaders “are incessantly invoking
reason.” Socialism illustrates for Le Bon how imperialism, rooted in the
aggressive nationalism of 1914, and internationalism, rooted in the mutinous
exhaustion of 1918, sustain themselves, in the supposed new world of the formal
peace, despite the illogic of their coexistence. Le Bon stakes out an
essentially conservative position: not that reason does not exist, but that
emotions and basic drives almost always trump reason in the behavior of large
groups of people. On the one hand, “The appearance of reason in the world is
comparatively recent”; on the other hand, “the appetites, feelings and passions
hark back to the origins of life, so that it is only natural that they, by
their hereditary accumulation, should have acquired a weight with which the
intellect is rarely strong enough to contend.”(4)
One remarks, however, that
everything that is not reason is not necessarily the opposite of reason. Morality,
for Le Bon, is not rational, but as a nation’s “internal discipline” it
functions as reason might, checking and deflecting disintegrative impulses. The
rebellion of which Socialism is the outward sign attacks even that dearly
bought heritage of “internal discipline,” with calamitous results.
Le Bon gives several examples of
the phenomenon. In Russia, “an empire of one hundred and seventy million souls,
which took centuries to shape, was destroyed in a few months by the action upon
primitive minds of those crude formulae which are often more destructive than
artillery.” The Germans and Austrians, thinking to have gained by the
dissolution of Russia, soon found, to their stupefaction, that the impartial
tide would sweep them away too. Le Bon credits the discipline of the American
Expeditionary Force with saving Britain and France from similar spreading
cataclysm. Then, inflated by what was almost a chance victory, Britain and
France became jealous of one another and predatory towards the defeated
enemies. They could agree only on the vengeful, profiteering cynicism of the
1919 Peace Conference and its Treaty. War, writes Le Bon, “completely reverses
the customary scale of values.” The total-war mentality of the combatant powers
would infect the nominal peace and not merely through the injustice of the
Versailles Treaty: “It is not only international morality that has
deteriorated, but also… the morality of the individual members of each nation. The
moral equipment has been more or less shattered everywhere.”
As would Oswald Spengler in The
Hour of Decision (1934), Le Bon denounces
the greed of the political wage, which unions extort from governments and
private enterprise alike by threats of work stoppages and hints of sabotage;
low productivity of unionized labor, once appeased, belongs to the greedy
pattern of the political wage. Everywhere a similar “mad race for wealth”
prevails, but without the discipline of thrift. Cynics seek easy gain; they
abuse credit. Governments, producing no real goods and therefore no real
wealth, pretend to solvency by printing money, so that “each fresh issue of
notes [corresponds] with a fresh diminution of output and fresh cravings for
enjoyment.” In one of The Psychology’s biological metaphors, almost every deliberate measure to allay
economic and social problems in the wake of the conflict has been maladaptive.
Technical advances, while
superficially evidence of progress in civilization, and while celebrated as
such, likewise generate unforeseen and maladaptive results; chiefly, in
connection with wire services and radio, they facilitate instantaneous
communications on a global scale. The Great War having depressed the average
intellectual acuity to an alarmingly low level, the new global audience stood
receptive not to argument and evidence but rather to the selfsame degraded cues
– the shibboleths and images – that most efficiently vector the “mental
contagion” which, according to Le Bon, animates a mindless collectivity. The
distance between the technical achievement and the ethical condition reflects
the principle that, “the great civilizations grow complex as they develop,
leaving behind them in their rapid progress a host of human beings who have not
the capacity to keep pace with them.” A constant propaganda of “equality,
wealth, and happiness” marshals that “host,” which might well be the majority,
into a classic proletariat. “We have innumerable leagues against alcoholism,
depopulation, etc.,” writes Le Bon, “but none has been founded to teach the
masses and to point out the economic realities that condition their life.”
III. The modern age since the French Revolution at the
latest is, in Le Bon’s view, an age of religious fervor, taking the term religion
in his special pejorative sense as a mob-like response to primitive stimuli, or
to “irreducible mystic ideas,” and thus also as a reactionary leap-backwards
from civilization. Many of Le Bon’s contemporaries shared the observation:
Spengler, for example, and the American writer-journalist T. Lothrop Stoddard
(1883 – 1950) whose Revolt against Civilization: The Menace of the Underman (1922) cites Le Bon and owes much to him. Le Bon in
his turn owed something to Joseph de Maistre (1753 – 1821) whose Considérations
sur la France (1796) and Soirées
du Saint Petersbourg (1821) examine the
French Revolution from an anthropological perspective, remarking the similitude
of insurrectionary bloodletting with ancient sacrificial practices. Although we
can see the sanguinary and cultic aspect of Lenin, Hitler, and Mao, and
although some analysts identify environmentalism and multiculturalism as
exhibiting traits of primitive religion, it remains difficult even for informed
conservative observers to grasp politicized modernity – from the Jacobins to
post-Constitutional America – in its entirety as religious to the core.
I have earlier quoted a sentence
from The World in Revolt that shows Le
Bon assimilating the Reformation and the French Revolution with “Islamism.” This
will shock most people even more than does describing modernity as essentially
religious. In Islam Le Bon finds the outstanding example of “mental contagion”
as “the instantaneous propagation of beliefs unsupported by any element of
reason.” Le Bon remarks with equal emphasis on the inability of Islam’s victims
to understand the power that confronted them. Civilized people assess fanatics
from a disadvantaged position: they cannot believe that arrogance and ferocity
correspond with inclination and capacity. Le Bon imagines the Sixth-Century
King of the Persians receiving “some Arab emissaries” who demand his
submission. “They are madmen,” the King says; “let them be sent away.” Three months later “the King of Kings is
cast down”; the Sassanid civilization, which traces its origins to the Sixth
Century BC, passes with him into the dust of history.
In The Psychology of Socialism (1896), Le Bon writes: “Whatever beliefs have once
reigned in the world – whether Christianity, Buddhism, or Islam, or merely some
political theory – they have only been propagated by the efforts of that
particular class of converts we call apostles. Hypnotised by the belief that
has conquered them, they are ready for every sacrifice that may propagate it,
and finally have no object in life but to establish its empire.” For Le Bon the
“apostles” are “démi-hallucinés.”
The World in Revolt returns to the subject of the destructive ferocity
that, “engendered by doctrines,” is “based on the hatred of any sort of
superiority, whether of wealth or… intellect.”(5) Le Bon cites by way
of topical illustration various barbaric incidents from Russia under the
Bolsheviks. He records the intolerance of all variants of militant socialism
for one another. Thus the Bolsheviks piled vilification on the parliamentary
socialists under the short-lived Alexander Kerensky regime and in the Soviet
press the Bolsheviks continuously heaped insults on all non-Bolshevik socialist
parties elsewhere in the world. The actual goal of socialism lies not in any
utopian scheme, which socialists might seek to realize in detail, but rather in
“absorption by the state” of everything – all conceivable institutions and
along with them private conscience that emerged, in the West, in the Middle
Ages. “Absorption” means destruction; the motive for destruction is envy elevated to a metaphysical
principle. “The Bolshevik mentality,” Le Bon writes, “is as old as history,”
the Biblical Cain having “had the mind of a Bolshevik.”
Le Bon writes: “Until the time,
which is probably distant, when the truths which I have expressed are regarded
as obvious, Bolshevism will continue to increase, absorbing the vast legion of
the unadapted: discontented teachers, indifferent workers, envious pupils of
the elementary schools; in other words, the alarming mass of vanity, incapacity
and hatred of which the world is full.” In another of The World in Revolt’s metaphors, Le Bon likens Bolshevism to the absurd
totems of the antique kingdoms. Like equality, “the serpent, the bullock, the
crocodile and other animals have had millions of worshippers” and “innumerable
were the divinities who demanded human sacrifice.”
Where Bolshevism does not yet
prevail, the swelling State nevertheless continues to assimilate institutions
and customs. Bureaucracy kills off invention and prosperity less swiftly than
insurrectionary socialism, but its hostility to freedom battens on the society
just as fatally in the long run. Again, the Great War drove the organization of
life under state control; and no state but one (the United States) seems
capable of shaking itself loose from the untoward transformation. Among “The
Perils of State Intervention,” as one of The World in Revolt’s chapters sets out, are: the inevitable atrophy of
private initiative under layers of stifling regulation and a resulting
“commercial decadence”; “incompetent agents” intruding their dictates into all
domains in order “to tax, regulate, and prohibit”; and finally “the autocracy
of an anonymous caste,” which “presses heavily upon the lives of citizens
compelled to support it.”
Contemporary readers will
probably react to Le Bon’s description of governmentally top-heavy societies
with a sigh of weary recognition.
In The World in Revolt, Le Bon fears most for his own country, France, and
opines that the United States – for him the quintessentially pragmatic nation –
will likely disencumber itself of the wartime political machinery. After a
second Great War, a so-called Cold War, and an infantile spasm of the
electorate, however, Le Bon’s picture of a stultified quasi-socialist society
well fits the current United States.
That, in 1921, Le Bon so
clairvoyantly knew what would happen should socialism and statism prevail might
lead one to pose the question, if the chain of cause and effect were so
obvious, with the implementation of invidious doctrines issuing in nothing but
“irremediable decadence,” then how would such doctrines contrive to persist
beyond their obvious dolorous effects? Especially how should they persist into
the present moment, which, despite the failure of their largest experiment, the
Soviet Union, seems suicidal in its eagerness to speed again down the same path
of utopian delusion? What makes the “démi-hallucinés” so fixed in their visions? Le Bon is ready with his
by now familiar answer: “If we wish to understand how educated men can become
victims of illusions, of which some, at least, could not bear the most
superficial examination, we must always remember that Socialism is a religion
much more than a doctrine, so that all arguments derived from reason or
experience are necessarily powerless to affect it. The convinced Socialist
believes in the Gospel of Karl Marx as the Mussulman believes in the Koran.”
IV. One could add that the terrible illusions persist not only through
being privatively religious in Le Bon’s sense, hence immune to logical
dissolution, but also because of their rootedness in resentment, which is the
most powerful and primal of all negative emotions, as the story of Cain and Abel
strives to tell. Marxism, feminism, environmentalism, and multiculturalism –
the rampant variants and hybrids of socialism – begin, in fact, not by
deflecting resentment, but rather by making it the center of existence, a
gesture that occurs already in the work of Jean-Jacques Rousseau. In the moment
of writing The World in Revolt, Le Bon judged that “mystic
elements” had prevailed: “Internationalists, Socialists, Bolsheviks and other
theorists, the champions of peace between the peoples but of civil war in the
interior of the nations… have undertaken a crusade against society as sinister
as the [late] German crusade against the independence of peoples.” A new mystic
formula, “The Society of Nations,” had
emerged in the diplomatic mess of euphoria and grudge holding after the
armistice. In their recoil from the war, the multitudes and their leaders
seized on that formula and began to be organized by it, the way all crowds
coalesce around totemic notions of minimal semantic content.
Whereas concerning the new mystic
formula “the German philosophers condemn it” and “the diplomatists distrust
it”; nevertheless as Le Bon writes, “the Socialist dreamer… regards it as the
regenerator of the human race.”
Insofar as any genuine
possibility of realization attached itself to the “semi-radiance” of the
regenerating idea, Le Bon saw it only “in a phase of evolution… still distant.”
In the meantime, however, under the idea’s influence and using the prestige of
the post-Armistice Peace Conference, bevies of hallucinating politicians had
“conceived the idea of rearranging the equilibrium of the world, forgetting
that such an equilibrium is the work of centuries.” The future boded ill. The
break-up of Austria-Hungary, when its apparatus of organization and its
traditions were sorely needed, punitive reparations laid against Germany, the
powder-keg of the Danzig settlement: these things guaranteed near-term chaos,
resentment, and conflict. Add to the destabilized international politics
stemming from the Great War the technical possibilities in new weaponry –
“whole fleets and armies could be instantly destroyed” – and the likelihood of
a nightmare world, as Le Bon sees it in the moment, only increases.(6)
The vagueness of occult symbols and the stupidity of the masses will exacerbate
everything, as “the nations and their rulers are swept off their feet by
passions and beliefs.” The remainder of the Twentieth Century largely bore out
Le Bon’s misgivings.
In the aftermath of another world
war, acute people like Albert Camus sensed again, at a new pitch, what Le Bon
had sensed in the early 1920s: the transformation of life into a topsy-turvy of
self-ordering rationality. In The Myth of Sisyphus (1942) and The Rebel [L’homme revolté], Camus calls this condition “the Absurd.” In those
two books he links the Absurd to the issues respectively of suicide and murder, failing however in The Rebel clearly to disambiguate that latter term from killing. I have remarked how the title and language of Le
Bon’s World in Revolt anticipate
the title and the language of The Rebel, while yet Camus never mentions Le Bon. In The World in
Revolt, moreover, in a discussion of “class
hatred,” we find this comment, in connection with the hortators of socialism:
“Repeating the time-honored formulae of hope which cast a spell on humanity in
the dawn of history, they have returned to the Hebraic myth of the Promised
Land, and are undertaking yet once again the task of Sisyphus, who was condemned
by the gods continually to roll a rock to the summit of a mountain, whence it
invariably rolled back again.” Why could Camus not incorporate Le Bon’s work in
his own?
One answer is that where Le Bon
stands outside what he describes, addressing it as a moralist, Camus stands
inside it, addressing it as an advocate or at least as an apologist, and he
finds that he is hard pressed therefore to make a real critique of the
mentality that he calls, with no little sympathy, rebellious. Camus asserts that the ideological-totalitarian
state and the man who rebels against the structure of existence (the
“metaphysical rebel”) stand separate from one another and that the latter
directs his revolt against primarily the former. In The Rebel, Camus writes: “Revolution is only the logical
consequence of metaphysical rebellion, and we shall discover, in our analysis
of the revolutionary movement, the same desperate and bloody effort to affirm
the dignity of man in defiance of the things that deny its existence. The
revolutionary spirit thus undertakes the defence of that part of man which
refuses to submit.”
It is not exactly that Camus
fails to see much of what Le Bon saw, but rather that he feels the magnetism of
submission, the impulse to merge with shared
resentment – and thus with the crowd – against the structure of reality. Thus
in The Myth of Sisyphus, Camus
notes that his eponymous hero “was disposed to practice the profession of a
highwayman” and to have expressed “levity in regard to the gods.” Sisyphus is,
for Camus, “the proletarian of the gods,” a phrase that buys into rebellious
vocabulary.
None of this is meant
gratuitously to diminish Camus; it is meant merely to reveal Camus’ limitations
in comparison with Le Bon. Much of The Rebel, which follows The Myth of Sisyphus by ten years, is clearsighted, as in its discussion
of the French Revolution and the Terror. That grim sectary of Terror Louis de
Saint-Just, writes Camus, expressed in every one of his pronouncements for the
Committée “a profound passion… for unity.” According
to Saint-Just, anyone who might “threaten unity” is apriori a criminal in the eyes of the Revolution. Camus’ unity is, of course, Le Bon’s crowd. Saint-Just had discovered how to apply the
Rousseauvian yearning for primitive fusion over civilized individuation as an
instrument of political action. One might even say, of Camus, that his
presentation in The Rebel tantalizingly
anticipates a revaluation of his own values that he did not live to fulfill. Even
so, even in its brilliance, that presentation remains repetitive. Le Bon had
written all of it, or nearly all of it, thirty years before and earlier,
including an analysis of Saint-Just. Camus adds to the fund of understanding
his experience during the Second World War and immediately thereafter, which
affirms Le Bon without adding anything essential.
Le Bon, his prose unencumbered by the locutions of French-Hegelian dialectics or the chic vocabulary of “Absurdism,” gets to essentials more plainly than Camus – even granting that the “Absurdist” vocabulary is meaningful in its way. Le Bon retains his absolute priority.
[1] One of the few recent writers apart from Girard to mention Le Bon is the late Stephen J. Gould, whose Mismeasure of Man (1981) denounces the author of The Crowd as a “misogynist” who wrote, in Gould’s words, “what must be the most vicious attack on women in modern scientific literature.” Gould notes that Le Bon “was horrified by the proposal of some American reformers to grant women higher education on the same basis as men.” Gould mentions that Le Bon’s oeuvre “had a strong influence on Mussolini.” This sentence is probably the source of the Wikipedia remark. I call attention to the character of Gould’s terms: he has invoked two of the contemporary Left’s stock charges – misogynist and fascist. These terms are nothing less than crowd-coalescing slogans designed to arouse and cement collective hostility against a pariah. One might wonder, who is the fascist?
[2] This would explain the polysyllabic opacity of all so-called postmodern prose, especially that associated with the “Deconstruction” of the late Jacques Derrida, by which irate meaningless bludgeons meaning.
[3] In Le Bon’s reading, the Reformation is the cauldron of the nation-state as such; an actual nation only exists in the aftermath of the religious wars.
[4] Here Le Bon’s reasoning is close to that of David Hume and Edmund Burke; also to S. T. Coleridge and Richard Weaver, all of whom affirm the wisdom in settled custom and habit and the folly in overturning them.
[5] This phrase, “hatred of superiority,” or its grammatical and semantic equivalent, occurs also in the work of Nietzsche, Scheler, and Spengler.
[6] A reader of H. G. Wells, Le Bon refers perhaps to The War in the Air (1906), with its depiction of the aerial bombardment of cities and flotillas, and The World Set Free (1914), with its depiction of atomic bombs let loose on one another by the warring powers of Europe. Earlier in The World in Revolt, Le Bon makes an explicit reference to Wells’ War of the Worlds (1897).
thanks
Submitted by mpresley on Thu, 2010-01-14 23:23.
I appreciate Thomas Bertonneau's concise analysis of a thinker likely not too well known. Le Bon's name sometimes shows up in reference to other thinkers I've encountered, so this summary is very welcome. For instance, the late professor Milic Capek's comments on Le Bon's critique of Nietzsche's views anent the idea of eternal recurrence (found in the old Encyclopedia of Philosophy), and he is also referenced in H.T. Hansen's almost book length essay to Julius Evola's Men Among the Ruins. I'd like to add that some of his works can be found on the Web at the Project Gutenberg site.